Cinema
owes much to painting in both content and style. But
films, while often influenced by great works of art,
are more than just moving paintings. Critics like
Gilles Deleuze have long recognized this distinction.
Deleuze refers to the film medium not in terms of
"frames"—sequential static images
(like paintings in a row)—but as "photogrammes,"
images that are fundamentally time‑bound and
produce a state of consciousness in the viewer distinct
from that produced by a painting. Such a realization
is the basis for director Jean‑Luc Godard's
observation that "Cinema is truth 32 times a
second." Films have often taken painters and
painting as their subjects, and the difficulty that
inevitably dogs these attempts is the problem of presentation.
How do you "show" an artist painting without
boring your audience to death? Worse yet, how is the
creative process that underlies painting best illustrated
on film?
One
solution is to focus not on the artist and his work
but on the social and personal conditions around
him. Hence, one watches Basquiat (1996)
and sees the painter's life unfold against the background
of the 1980s art scene in New York City. Personal
circumstances also couch the narrative in films
like Vincent and Theo (1990) and Surviving
Picasso (1996). The expectation here
is that viewers will be sufficiently familiar with
their respective artists. The films can then concentrate
on "untold" stories like Van Gogh's relationship
with his brother or Picasso's torrid love life.
Films of this kind present their subjects indirectly
through the social and/or personal circumstances
of the painter's life and work. The success of such
a strategy is debatable, however.
Another
approach is to divorce the cinematic narrative from
the facts of the painter's life, work and social
context to construct a new, particularly cinematic
examination of all three. This, it seems, is the
idea behind Stephen Soderbergh's Kafka
(1991), an underrated interpretation of the life
and work of writer Franz Kafka that mixes types
and images from the author's writings with features
of his life.
Kafka
is not far in spirit from Derek Jarman's Caravaggio
(1986), a film that deals only partly with the life‑events
of Michelangelo Caravaggio. It draws the viewer's
attention away from historical context by including
modern anachronisms in the 17th‑century scene
(like a digital watch on a courtier's wrist). More
interestingly, Caravaggio imitates
the Italian artist in its visual style and punctuates
its narrative with filmic reproductions of his paintings
in an effort to lend images to the artist's creative
force.
Akira
Kurosawa used a similar approach in a portion of
his film Dreams (1990). In one of
the dreams, Kurosawa meets Vincent Van Gogh (played
with relish by Martin Scorsese). Far from a literal
depiction, the segment is surreal in form and content.
Kurosawa attempts to find Van Gogh "in"
his paintings: he walks on‑screen through
several of Van Gogh's better‑known compositions
toward a field where the artist is at work. Their
exchange is, of course, completely fantastical (Van
Gogh not only speaks to this contemporary filmmaker
but also with blackbirds). At the end of the segment,
the image freezes and the camera pans out to reveal
that the foregoing scene was a painting done by
Van Gogh—a painting which hangs on the wall
of a museum while Kurosawa admires it.
Films
that examine painting in this way tend to be the
most stimulating. By avoiding the confines of factual
reality, Jarman and Kurosawa widen the view into
their subjects' minds while skirting the inherent
problem of presentation—a problem also absent
from films directly influenced by a particular artistic
style or school.
The
rise of cinema, for instance, was contemporaneous
with the avant‑garde art movements of the
early part of our century, and the consequences
are not hard to see. Early German silents like The
Cabinet of Dr. Caligari (1919) and Nosferatu
(1922) were stylistic counterparts to the Expressionist
paintings of their day. They, in turn, influenced
film noir, arguably the most important American
contribution to cinema.
A
notable example of a painter intimately involved
in a film is Salvador Dali's set design for Alfred
Hitchcock's Spellbound (1945). Dali
created surreal effects to illustrate the mental
state of Gary Cooper's character whose psychological
trauma is diagnosed by Ingrid Bergman. The case
is actually a bit ironic in that Dali devoted himself
to a surrealism that defied rational explanation.
The film, however, is based on the supposition that,
no matter how weird things get in the human mind,
modern psychological science can make sense of just
about anything. So the fact that Cooper gets unreasonably
upset when Bergman runs a fork across a white tablecloth
can be explained by the fact that he accidentally
killed his own brother while skiing (parallel lines
on a white surface agitate him because they remind
him of ski tracks in the snow).
A
recent instance may demonstrate how the appearance
of a painting in a film can be subverted to the
intentions of the filmmaker. In his recent The
End of Violence (1997), Wim Wenders includes
a segment which depicts a movie shoot. The scene
being shot (the movie within the movie) is an exact
duplicate of Edward Hopper's Nighthawks,
the paradigmatic picture of mid‑century, urban
American alienation. In Wenders' version of the
painting, the beautiful blond at the diner's counter
shoots the soda jerk, the suggestion being that
violence and image‑media are deeply involved
in the peculiarly American isolation that Nighthawks
represents.
Others
have abandoned painting as their primary art in
favor of cinema. Peter Greenaway, creator of resplendent
films like The Cook, the Thief, His Wife, and
Her Lover (1989), Prospero's Books
(1991), The Macon Baby (1993) and
The Pillow Book (1997), began his
artistic career in painting, and, in fact, still
describes himself as a painter working in cinema.
He cites at least three reasons for making the move
to film:
Well,
I suppose the most obvious concern is that paintings
don't move. So we must embrace the notion of movement.
Apart from one or two obscure paintings by [Robert]
Rauschenberg which had in‑built transistor
radios, paintings don't deal with music. I have
an excitement, an attachment, to the way music and
the image can be integrated... And on the whole
painting does not deal with text. So for me cinema
is the ideal medium where I can engage in a notion
of playing with text and playing with image.
Anyone
who has seen Greenaway's work knows that these concerns
occupy the forefront of his aesthetic. It might
even be argued that Greenaway accomplishes a kind
of deconstruction of the screen by eschewing straight
realism for a cinema that capitalizes on all its
capabilities. He reiterates time and again that
cinema has been too much like illustrated text throughout
its history, naming only Abel Gance's Napoleon
(which, even in 1929, was experimenting with split
screens) as a prominent exception. With Greenaway,
we get picture‑in‑picture arrangements,
time‑defying constructions, contrasting film
stocks and surreal compositions, a style that's
principally about image and owes more to modern
painting than to the history of cinema.
Greenaway
argues that if film is to accommodate itself to
the new millennium and become an art form in its
own right, it must free itself from screenplays
and formulate images independently. He believes
painting, at least in part, holds the key to crafting
such a style. Hence, we find ourselves, once again,
in a position where painting constructs our cinema
aesthetic. Just as early films drew strength from
techniques and styles advanced by painters, perhaps
modern cinema can be refreshed through a renewed
exposure to and consideration of its kindred art.